Recent Discussion of the Capital Concept
by Frank A. Fetter
Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1900.
To most readers the reopening of the question as to the concept of capital will seem to call for an apology. If after so much discussion the fundamental definitions have not been generally agreed upon, some will say that further argument on terms and concepts is a waste of time. While practical questions of great importance await profounder study, impatience of metaphysical quibbling is pardonable; but in recent years many students have felt that there was need of earnest effort to make clearer and more consistent the fundamental concepts. These are the tools which aid men to think on economic subjects. A flaw in these concepts, an unsuspected ambiguity in a word or phrase, not only mars the conclusions of the student, but affects the popular judgment on the most practical questions. The circumstances and special problems of former generations have caused the grouping of unharmonized ideas under one term; and it is the business of the economist to measure, mark, and correct the concepts, to make the parts content with each other and the whole fitted to the needs of social discussion. The writer believes that there is no economic term to which this statement applies more fully than to capital, and this belief is the apology for the present paper. The concept of capital holds a central place in every economic system, and on its treatment have always depended the leading categories in the theory of economics, All agree, whatever definition may be held, that! this is increasingly "a capitalistic age," The place, therefore, of the concept in all practical problems is growing more and more dominant; and a better definition of it is the most urgent need of the abstracter branch of economic science.
I. Böhm-Bawerk
A point of departure admirably fitted for our purpose is found in
the Positive Theory of Capital of Böhm-Bawerk, which was given to the
English reading public in 1891, and at once gained a large following, There
are several advantages in beginning here. As the author's purpose was to
present not only a theory of interest, but, as the title indicates, a Positive
Theory "of Capital," we get the most typical cross-section of the
study. We start with the known; and we direct our criticisms not against
abandoned errors, but against views widely accepted.
Böhm-Bawerk undertook in his two large volumes to deal thoroughly
with the theories of interest, and, to do so, was led to deal with the concepts
of capital; for, thought he, it is capital for which interest is paid. However
much he disputed the relation of production and interest, he had no doubt,
in undertaking his study,(1*) as to the relation of capital and interest,
Interest is the yield of capital in the broader sense, and capital the source
of interest. They are correlative terms. To clear the field for his own concept
of capital, Böhm-Bawerk, therefore, passes in review the various conceptions
of capital that have been employed. He begins by following the historical
order,(2*) and later groups the concepts in logical order.(3*) In the chapter
on historical development he begins with a mention of the medieval view of
capital as "an interest-bearing sum of money," gives a few words
to Turgot's "saved goods" (a very inadequate, not to say mistaken,
interpretation of Turgot's view), and passes on to Adam Smith's division
of these into consumption goods and capital that brigs an income. In Smith's
treatment the author think he finds the germ of the productivity theory of
interest, which he considers false. Smith, in giving two varieties of the
concept, -- capital as a means of acquisition to the individual, and capital
as a means of social production, -- has in reality given, says Böhm-Bawerk,
"two entirely independent conceptions, resting substantially on quite
different foundations, and only connected externally by a very loose bond."(4*)
After devoting several pages to discussing this difficulty, the author abandons
the historical order, and enumerates eight other variations of the concept:
Hermann's "every durable foundation of a utility which has exchange
value"; Menger's "groups of economic goods of higher rank [productive
goods] now available to us for future periods," Kleinwächter's
"tools of production"; Jevons's "sustenance of the laborer";
Marx's "instruments for the exploitation of the laborer"; Knies's
goods available to satisfy wants in the future; Walras's goods which can
be used more than once; McLeod's "value of the productive power contained
in material goods,"(5*) These are discussed more at length in Chapter
V, the most important contentions being that the distinction between consumption
goods and what he calls "the true instrument of production" is
essential; that labor must not be confused with capital; that land must for
many important reasons also be kept distinct; and that capital should be
looked upon not as a "sum of value" hovering over goods, but as
the "complex of goods" itself.(6*)
Among these many variations the author gives his approval to that of Adam Smith, giving it "a more distinct formulation,"(7*) however, and distinguishing between the wider and narrower conceptions, acquisitive (private) and productive (social) capital. Of the former he says: "Capital in general we shall call a group of Products which serve as means to the Acquisition of Goods. Under this general conception we shall put that of Social Capital as narrower conception."(8*) The problem of interest, he thinks, is connected with private or acquisitive capital, not necessarily with social or productive capital. We may represent in the above diagram the results of the author's long inquiry, The large circle represents the entire material wealth of society, The outer band marked L is land, or all natural agents, The entire circle P contained within that band consists of "products," The next band, CG, is consumption goods. The concentric circle SC, within, is social capital, and the oval C is "capital in general," or private capital, embracing all social capital and, in addition, such consumption goods as are let for hire, Representing this in another way, we have the following classification: --
What judgment now is to be passed on this reading of the capital concept?
We must be struck by the fact that in the matter of simplicity the results
of the author's study are not ideal. But he asserts with a tone of triumph
that the "conception meets all our logical and terminological requirements.
Logically, it is unassailable."(9*) He concludes with this hopeful prophecy:
"If, then, unbiassed people are ever to agree on the conception of capital,
we may expect that this will be the one chosen."(10*) His strongest
ground for such a hope was the fact that he had made a place under the name
"capital" for the two most generally employed concepts, and that
the concept of social capital is the one widely held, -- "products used
for further production." He did not claim much originality for this
part of his work. He says: "The heavy part of the Positive Theory of
Capital lies in the theory of interest. In the other portions of the subject
[he seems to mean the concept of capital] I was able, at least on the whole,
to follow in the footsteps of previous theorists."(11*)
The immediate reception of this portion of the author's work largely
justified his hopes, His careful restatement of the concept and the authority
of his name undoubtedly added to the prestige it already enjoyed. The more
usual point of attack on the author has been his interest theory, not his
capital concept, which has been far less questioned,(12*) -- in fact, has
usually been accepted as flawless. Some protests, however, have already been
raised against it; and, although it is still the dominant concept, discontent
with this and other features of the older economic thought has been spreading.
The earnest teacher, using the available text-books, and attempting to correct
their treatment in accord with recent criticisms, is in despair. To one who
has watched the course of the discussion it might seem that the service of
Böhm-Bawerk's work, so far as it touches the capital concept, lay not
in settling, but in reopening the whole question. Remembering, however, that
most students still accept Böhm-Bawerk's statement of the concept, we
turn to a group of thinkers who would give other reading to it; and we shall
confine our study to the leading representatives of two differing views on
the question.
II. J.B. Clark
This part of the Austrian writer's work, especially, was attacked
by Professor John B, Clark,(13*) who defends the productivity theory of interest,
though that point we need not raise in this paper. His own views had been
published(14*) at the same time as the German edition of the Positive Theory
of Capital; but more attention was attracted to them, it is probable, as
a result of this controversy than at their first publication. I shall not
enter into the merits of the discussion as a whole. It was carried on with
great skill, with some later confessed misunderstanding, and at times, perhaps,
with an over-subtlety which makes it exceedingly difficult to follow. I shall
simply try to state the issue involved as to the capital concept.
In every-day speech and in the writing of economists there have been,
since before the time of Adam Smith, two broadly marked ways of thinking
of capital: one views it as concrete goods, such as tools and machines; the
other, as the money expression, or market value, of the goods, It is probable
that no writer has long kept from the use of the term in both these ways,
no matter what his formal definition. Frequently both uses will be found
on the same page. A few writers only have chosen to frame their capital concept
in accord with the second of these ways of thinking,(15*) Böhm-Bawerk
has taken the former way, defining capital as the concrete goods; and in
the interest problem he insists on the need of comparing goods of like kind
and quantity. Clark declares this to be an error, and defines capital in
harmony with the second way of thinking of it. He says, "There is in
existence a permanent fund of productive wealth, expressible in money, but
not embodied in money; and it is this that business men designate by the
term capital."(16*) The concrete thing which make up this fund he calls
"capital goods." In contrast with this list of goods he often speaks
of his kind of capital as "true capital," or "pure capital,"
which, as he says elsewhere, "resides in many unlike things, but consists
of a single entity that is common to them all. That entity is 'effective
social utility.'"(17*) Again, he says: "Capital goods are... vanishing
elements. True capital: "is abiding."(18*) Elsewhere he clothes
his definition, which he calls "the common and practical sense of the
term," in these words: "Capital is an abiding fund of wealth employed
in production."(19*)
Needless to say, Böhm-Bawerk defends himself vigorously against
the charge of "side-tracking" the theory of capital in defining
the concept as he had done. The controversy turned about the phrase "goods
of like kind and quantity," and the question as to the real nature of
the comparison of present and future goods. Clark holds that it is two sums
of "quite different goods" that are compared. Böhm-Bawerk
saves his phrase by the expedient of making the "goods of like kind
and quantity" mean "dollars," "exactly as does Professor
Clark."(20*) This is not a novelty with him; for, as he points out,(21*)
he had "in many, and in some of the most important, passages of the
Positive Theory of Capital... used money as an illustration of the proposition
that present are worth more than future goods." Without quite indorsing
Clark's comment on this point, we may agree with him that this appears to
surrender the entire question conceding the formula "of like kind and
quantity."(22*) What meaning is in the phrase "the technical superiority
of present goods over future goods," when those goods are made to mean
dollars? What becomes of the elaborate analysis of the roundabout method
of production?(23*) Certainly, it means something very different, when the
present goods employed are taken merely as circulating medium which is not
in the normal case retained by the individual producers nor used up by society.
The truth is, Böhm-Bawerk had fallen into the common error of using
two different conceptions of capital, and at the first attack was found in
an untenable position. This phase of the controversy seems to end by showing
that the conception of capital made use of by Böhm-Bawerk himself, when
he discusses business problems, takes the money expression, and differs in
important ways from that of concrete goods expressed in his elaborately framed
definition. A word as to the relation of these two views. It is to be noted
that both parties agree that economists must study wealth under both these
aspects. Böhm-Bawerk admits that he does so. The point against him is
that, while framing his concept and basing his argument as to interest on
the first, he introduces the second view, in some ways inconsistent, without
recognizing the shift of concept. And Clark says that "the issue is
not whether concrete capital goods are or are not to be studied at all. For
certain purposes they have to be studied."(24*) But he would confine
the term "capital" to the sum of wealth or "permanent fund"
constituted of the perishable goods.
The conception championed by Clark is of great significance; and, before
going further, it is important to consider some peculiarities and difficulties
in Clark's way of setting it forth.
(1) The discussion is confined by Clark at the outset to social capital.(25*)
He uses this term in a wider sense than Böhm-Bawerk does (as is explained
in the next paragraph), but not differently as to the exclusion of consumption
goods. Social capital is that kind which Böhm-Bawerk himself considers
to be productive. Clark gains thus a distinct tactical advantage over his
opponent in upholding the productivity theory of interest, though that is
not of immediate importance to us here. The fact, however, that Böhm-Bawerk
does not note this limitation, but fights the issue on the ground chosen
by his adversary, shows that he himself is caught in the confusion of the
two concepts, and is the strongest evidence of the inexpediency of the division
of capital into social and private.(26*) On the other hand, the fact is of
immediate interest to us that Clark gives this narrower content to the term
"capital," confining capital to "material forms of wealth
that do not directly minister to consumers' wants,"(27*) and does not
make a place for acquisitive consumption goods, nor explain the interest
from them, as is done by Böhm-Bawerk in his concept of private capital.
In this respect the concept evidently needs addition or correction.
(2) In the second place, Clark's explanation of the genesis of capital
is inconsistent with his own concept. Land used productively -- for example,
a farm, a waterfall, a mine, any rare and useful natural agent -- is capital
according to his definition. In his earlier utterances, such thing are in
plain words included.(28*) In the later articles this is still the inevitable
implication of the definition, "a fund of productive wealth expressible
in money"; but a reader new to the author's doctrine would find no specific
statement to this effect, and there would be small chance that the meaning
in question would be gathered. The whole logic of the argument is against
it. "The genesis of capital," we are told, "takes place by
a process for which the good old term 'abstinence' is, as I venture to maintain,
the best designation."(29*) This does not seem to give a place in capital
to natural agents. There are, we are told, two classes of accumulators: the
typical capitalists, who save to make permanent additions to their capital;
and the quasi-capitalists, who "save sums now, intending to spend them
later."(30*) There is no place here for the unearned increment of a
newly discovered mine, which to-day forms for many men the chief productive
wealth expressible in money, If this is saving, it is a sense so unusual
as to require a special explanation by the author; and it is difficult to
see how it can consistently be given. There certainly would be no attempt
to evade the real question by assuming that the dollars that bought the mine
had been saved; for the mine may not have been sold, and, if so, it is irrelevant
to the issue. If the definition adopted by Clark is consistently applied,
there are necessarily many things forming a part of capital which never have
been saved, and which never have called for abstinence, as Clark employs
that term.(31*) In fact, Clark seems to show here, as did Böhm-Bawerk,
some traces of the error of the labor theory of value, so difficult to throw
off.(32*)
(3) Again, Clark would seem to err by extreme statement in making it
in the nature of capital to be a "permanent fund," "In creating
capital, we put the personal good away from us forever... An addition to
the social fund of perpetual capital is brought into existence." "Nothing
generates capital that does not add to the permanent fund of invested wealth."(33*)
"True capital... is, in the absence of untoward accidents, perpetual,
and yields perpetual fruits,"(34*) Many other expressions emphasize
the same thought. Now this evidently does not apply at all to the author's
quasi-capitalist, who saves to spend later. That, of course, is why he uses
the term "quasi," which evades the issue. Either such savings are
capital (in which case why quasi?) or they are not capital, and may be omitted
from the concept. The author, after stating that a part of the accumulation
of capital is due to these quasi-capitalists proceeds as if there were none
such. If better or more tools and larger stock were accumulated, and were
then allowed to deteriorate while in use without being replaced, our author
must certainly call them capital while they lasted; and, if so, the element
of permanency is no essential part of the capital concept. Indeed, if a fund
of productive wealth must be permanent to be capital, we cannot be sure that
there is any such a thing; for we have not the gift of prophecy, and all
human interests are fleeting.(35*) Clark himself says, "Capital... normally
will never perish"; but "this is not saying that no capital ever
perishes in fact."(36*) This says clearly enough that permanency is
not an essential mark of the concept, and makes meaningless both the word
itself in that connection and a number of sentences, besides those quoted,
in which this feature is emphasized as a vital mark of the concept. There
is a valid thought in his contention, but it is not that capital is in its
nature perpetual. There is ambiguity in the phrases "increase of capital"
and "decrease of capital," because they may mean either some of
the parts or the whole. A part of capital may perish while the total amount
of capital is preserved or even increased. Clark would confine the expression
to the whole of capital, and objects to the form of statement "capital
is destroyed" when the value of the concrete goods is passed on to other
goods. But what of the cases where the total value is not preserved? The
zeal of his attack carries him to an extreme and untenable expression, and
makes him insist upon an unessential.(37*)
(4) Less successful than his contention against Böhm-Bawerk about
"goods of like kind and quantity" is Clark's claim that capital
"synchronizes all industry and its fruition," that because of capital
"industry and its fruition are simultaneous." There are several
objections to such an expression.
(a) I am not quite in sympathy with the point of view of either of the
parties to the discussion, but between them it is a question not as to what
happens, -- not of fact, -- but of expression; and Böhm-Bawerk's opinion
commends itself when he says(38*) it is a "figure of speech" that
is "misleading" to say that the real wages, consisting of "consumption
goods" revived to-day for work done on goods not to be completed for
years, are the "true and immediate fruit" of, e.g., the tanner's
labor.(39*) To the tanner, of course, they are the "immediate"
and only fruits, since they are all he gets for his labor, The question is,
does it seem logical and expedient from the general standpoint in economic
discussion to consider and speak of them as the "true fruits" of
that day's labor? The expression chosen appears to say merely that these
things express the present market value of the laborer's services; that is,
it is a roundabout and somewhat whimsical way of stating the truism that
they are the man's wages.
(b) Further, it may be urged that the inaptness of this expression is
more apparent when something other than subsistence goods are considered.
In the example chosen of the tanner, it is at least debatable whether it
is best to call the shoes he gets to-day the "true fruit" of his
labor. But in the case of the laborer receiving food and clothing for digging
a canal or working on a marble palace, it is straining the point further
to use the expression. If here, too, his wages are called the "true
fruit" of his labor, it still appears that the peculiar power ascribed
to capital is due only to one part of capital, the finished consumption goods.
No matter how large a stock of capital in the form of machines, buildings,
and raw materials may be on hand, if there be no stock of finished goods,
labor and its results are not synchronized.(40*)
(c) A further objection to this way of conceiving of the nature of capital's
work is that it would, if true, be applicable only to "produced"
forms of capital. As indicated by the phrases "industry and its fruition,"
"labor and its fruits," it implies vaguely the labor theory of
value as to the origin of capital. The picture of labor continuously flowing
into the reservoir of capital and consumption goods at the same time flowing
out(41*) is not satisfactory as applied to products; for it implies that
the inflow of a quantity of labor forces out consumption goods whose quantity
is determined or measured by the quantity of inflowing labor. The value of
consumption goods flowing out, however, is greater in varying degrees than
the value of labor flowing in; and it is only through their values that we
can compare at all the quantities of the two streams. Further, it is not
a happy figure; for it suggests that all the goods that are a part of capital
will eventually become consumption goods, whereas in many cases this is not
expected nor desired. It is significant that Clark in describing the process
speaks only of "the materials, raw and partly wrought," of which
an article for consumption is made. He ignores machines and durable goods.
It is only in the gradual passing on of their value, as they are used up,
to the thing that are made by them, that machines and more durable agents
can be said to ripen at all.(42*) Even Clark's value conception of capital,
however, though it explains this point better than does the concrete concept
of capital, does not avoid the difficulty. The point may be most clearly
seen in the case of natural agents, which, as we have noted, are in Clark's
treatment included in the "fund" of capital. If we consider not
merely capital in the form of products more or less fitted for consumption,
but, as his concept requires, durable natural agents also, the phrases we
are criticising appear hardly short of absurd. Clark forgets this kind when
he says: "The capital goods that are set working are not permanent.
They pass away, and are replaced."(43*) Natural agents, the field, the
waterfall, in so far as they are thought of apart from betterments upon them,
have not been originated by labor; and they are not in a state of transformation
that will eventually ripen them into consumption goods. They stand there
to be used by man, if he wishes, as an aid in securing future harvests or
products; but neither the thing themselves nor their value or money expression
are "synchronizing" labor and its fruits. If there is any synchronizing,
it is done not by this, but by some other part of capital, and is, therefore,
not an essential mark of the capital concept.
(5) It is likely that to some points in what has been thus far said the
answer will be made that they are due to misunderstanding of the author's
meaning. No doubt the author attaches great weight to the contrast he draws
between true capital and capital goods, which it might seem I had neglected.
The reply is a criticism stronger, perhaps, than any of the foregoing against
Clark's capital concept. There is in his mode of thinking of this contrast
an over-abstraction that is neither expedient nor logical; and there results
in his presentation some inconsistency of thought and statement. In some
passages, capital is said to be as concrete a thing as can be. It "consists
in goods. It is not an abstraction, and it is not a force independently of
matter. It has substance. If at any instant we could collect in one place
all the material forms of wealth that do not directly minister to consumers'
wants, we should have the fund for the moment before our eyes in substantial
embodiment."(44*) Capital is thus " productive wealth, expressible
in money, but not embodied in money."(45*) That is plain enough, and
we are still on solid ground: we are not puzzled here by the "entity,
effective social utility," of the earlier statement,(46*) where capital
does not consist of the concrete thing, but is the "fund that resides
in many unlike things," and is "embodied in instruments of production."
This has the unpleasant flavor of Marx's labor jelly, though it need not
be taken as more than a loose, convenient way of expressing the market value
of the concrete things. But the development that follows of the paradoxical
contrasts between capital goods and true capital appears to be mischievous
subtlety, The very adjectives "true" and "pure" applied
to capital are suspicious. Why not plain "capital"? We are told
that "the genesis of capital goods is unlike that of capital."(47*)
It would seem that, if capital consists of concrete goods, then making concrete
goods is making capital. But the author says not, unless those goods are
net additions to the stock; that is, more than replace the capital destroyed
in the same time. "Build an altogether new engine. That is creating
capital. Renewing an old one is only preserving capital."(48*) The simple
mode of expression that some capital has been created, while an equal amount
has been destroyed, is thus not to be permitted. Surely, since capital has
substance and consists in goods, there is only one way in which its amount
can be preserved while some of it is being destroyed; and that is, by "creating"
more capital to replace that destroyed. And what would be the circle within
which the balance must be struck? Would it be the individual, the national,
or the world economy? If John builds a machine while his neighbor lets one
decay, then has John created no capital? It is true that care is often needed,
in speaking of any increase, to indicate whether it is a net increase or
not, but no more needed in the case of a "fund of capital" than
in that of a herd of cattle. The striking antithesis of the goods that make
up capital with the capital itself appears thus to be over-abstraction and
unreality. To sum up the objections to Clark's conception of capital:(49*)
--
(1) It includes only goods used in "production" and does not
recognize nor prepare to explain the interest bearing qualities of consumption
goods.
(2) It is confused in attributing the genesis of capital to abstinence
(as he uses that word) while including in capital natural agents for whose
origin no abstinence was required.
(3) It errs in making permanency, or perpetuity, an essential mark of
capital.
(4) The statement that an important, if not the chief, function of capital
is to "synchronize industry and its fruition" is a misleading figure
of speech, It can be affirmed, even figuratively, only of the part of produced
goods that is to be at once consumed, and is quite meaningless as applied
to the durable natural agents which are a part of his capital concept.
(5) The conception, starting from concrete goods, is developed away from
them into a more abstract, dematerialized "pure" or "true"
capital, which is put into contrast with real things.
III. Irving Fisher.
We now turn to the notable contribution of Professor Irving Fisher.(50*)
He lays a basis for his own treatment with sound statements as to the requisites
of a good definition, and careful studies of the definitions and usage of
the leading authorities. He believes that a mistake has been made as to the
real character of the problem, that it is not one of the classification of
wealth, and that unavoidable difficulties "attend every effort to delimit
capital from 'other wealth.'"(51*) His own conclusion, then, is that
capital should be taken to mean simply all wealth at a point of time.(52*)
It is contrasted not with other wealth, -- for that category is exhausted,
-- but with the same wealth as a flow during a given period, and at a rate.
The contrast, then, is between a stock and a flow, and still more important
"between stock and rate of flow."(53*) This conception is ingeniously
developed, use being made of mathematical terminology, and is applied in
criticism of rival definitions. Finally, the attempt is made to show how
it could be employed in the discussion of various economic questions. To
grasp more fully the import of this radical proposal in economic terminology,
let us note in what regards it differs from the conceptions we have been
considering.
(1) Its content is wider than that of any foregoing concept, Böhm-Bawerk
excludes all natural agents and most consumption goods from his wider concept,
private capital, and excludes the other consumption goods used in acquisition
from the narrower concept of social capital. Clark appears at first to include
all natural agents, though excluding all consumption goods, then treats capital
as if it originated only in labor, and did not include natural agents, and
finally mystifies us by his contrast of capital goods and pure capital, leaving
us in doubt whether he would include any concrete things as such. Fisher's
concept takes them all in, sweeps down the wall between the old concept of
capital and consumption goods on the one hand and natural agents on the other.
To my mind this suggestion is the most fertile part of Fisher's discussion.
(2) It agrees with Böhm-Bawerk's and differs from Clark's conception
in considering that the concrete things should be estimated by physical measurements,
and not in. The objection to Clark's view their money expression, in this
regard, he says, "is not that this summation of value is inadmissible,
but that it is a secondary operation. Objects of capital are antecedent to
the value of those objects... Wheat must be measured in bushels before it
is measured in dollars."(54*) He, therefore, finds it a "serious
objection to Clark's definition" that he endeavors "to include
different sorts of capital in the same fund, reduced to a common equivalent
in terms of value." Here, in my opinion, is a radical defect in Fisher's
view. (a) It is true that wheat must "be measured in bushels before
it can be measured in dollars," but it must also be tested for quality.
One will not value as highly a small apple as a large one, a sour as a sweet
one, a rotten as a sound one. We could thus say that apples must be measured
in sweetness before being measured in value. But an inventory of all possible
measurable qualities, while helpful in estimating, would not itself express
the amount of capital, for the things might after all have no value at all.
(b) Though an intelligible description of the quantity of any single kind
of goods could be made in such terms, yet the total quantity of many different
kinds of goods cannot be expressed for economic purposes in a single sum
excepting in terms of value. A capital account in which five pounds of feathers
were added to a bushel of wheat and a yard of cloth would give a curious
total. (c) Fisher is inevitably betrayed into inconsistency when he Comes
to estimate the quantities of wealth, and express in percentages the relation
between the stock and rate of flow, for this can be done only by comparison
of values.(55*)
(3) This conception shares what I believe to be an error, common with
it to both of the others,(56*) in that it makes the income of a community
consist of "streams... of the very same commodities"(57*) that
compose the total capital. This, again, implies that all things of value
originate in labor, and are on their way towards the goal of consumption
goods: whereas many things, standing where they are, may be made to push
other things towards that goal, though never getting nearer to it themselves;
e.g., machines and natural agents, Fisher means by income a "flow of
things" (material things), and rejects Mr Edwin Cannan's conception
"of income as a flow of pleasure," or satisfactions.(58*) The book-keeping
of society will be thrown badly out of balance if services be not counted
as a part of income; but, even if services be included as a part both of
income and of capital at a point of time, there are still many things, as
above indicated, that are a part of Fisher's capital only, and never are
a part of the flow of income. They never have been made for consumption,
and never will be fitted for consumption.
(4) A final objection is that the term "Capital" is made synonymous
with wealth, and two good words are employed in the same sense. Fisher anticipates
this objection, and recognizing its validity, if the fact be true, defends
by saying that wealth presents the two aspects of income and stock (capital),
-- differences important enough to merit separate terms. This defence fails,
if the point made in the preceding paragraph is sound. By wealth, Fisher
must mean here "all wealth." As I have shown, all capital must
be considered wealth, and all wealth capital by Fisher's definition, though
all wealth has not been nor will all wealth become income. Wealth and capital
thus are synonymous, while income differs from them not merely as an aspect,
but in the group of goods which composes it.
The concept under discussion is credited in part to Professor Simon Newcomb,
is indorsed in the main by Mr Edwin Cannan, and has received the approval
of Professor Hadley in his Economics. Its merits and the ability of its presentation
by Fisher have surely attracted other followers to one or another feature
of it. It has therefore a worthy standing among the competing conceptions.
Some portions of the presentation are most illuminating, and must be looked
upon as distinct contributions to economic theory. Careful distinction between
a stock of capital regularly employed, the turn-over in a business, and the
income from a business have not always been made; and confusion has resulted.
But this difficulty is not such as to call for the construction of the capital
concept with that distinction as the central thought. On the whole, there
is little probability that this conception will triumph, its defects both
as to consistency and expediency being of an essential nature, its points
of merit being capable of adaptation to another and better central thought.
We now have finished our review of the more notable recent conceptions, rivals
to that put forward by Böhm-Bawerk. Though confined to a few names,
it has necessarily taken a somewhat wide range in the points considered.
It is hoped to use the fruits of this study in the next two divisions, in
which the analysis of Böhm-Bawerk's conception is resumed. I shall then
go on to formulate more positively a capital concept which will be free,
I trust, from the many objections that have been considered.
IV. Private and Social Capital: An Illogical Distinction
I have sought in the foregoing to give a clear statement to the capital
concept of Böhm-Bawerk and its recent rivals, those of Professors Clark
and Fisher, to show the main points of difference, and finally to criticize
in some detail the conceptions of these later writers. We are now prepared
to return to the criticism of Böhm-Bawerk's views which were the starting-point
of our study, and, taking up more thoroughly than before some of the issues
involved in his definition, to work towards a positive conclusion.
The distinction between private and social capital is considered by Böhm-Bawerk
to be of the very greatest importance, and he deems his clear distinguishing
of them to be one of his highest services to economic theory. The failure
to distinguish them, he thinks, is the chief reason for the "false"
productivity theory of interest. If the difference is not seen between capital,
the source of interest, and capital, the tool in production, interest, he
argues, is naturally thought to be due to productivity. But, if it is clearly
seen that a part of interest-bearing capital is not a tool in production,
then productivity cannot be the one essential explanation of interest. This
point was evaded by Clark, as I have shown;(59*) for he simply considers
social or productive capital, and omits mention of acquisitive consumption
goods. It was not raised in his discussion with Clark by Böhm-Bawerk
himself, for his attention was fixed on other points; but in his reply to
Walker it is put very clearly. "There is interest without any production
whatever... I refer, for example, to interest on consumption loans and to
the return on durable consumption goods, such as rented houses, pianos, and
the like."(60*) Private capital is, by his view, social or productive
capital plus some other things, enjoyable and more or less durable products
let for hire to the user. Of what importance is this class of goods that
makes all the difference between the two concepts? He has here mentioned
rented houses and pianos: the stock illustration is the masquerade suit let
by the costumer. A complete list of these articles would include a very small
amount of wealth compared with that in social capital, and, doubtless, very
much less than that in the rest of consumption goods. Yet it would be wrong
to claim on this account that it is not worth while to make a difference
in the concept. Logical differences of any importance call for distinctions
in concepts, no matter how slight be the quantitative differences. I pass,
therefore, to a criticism of the logical grounds for such a distinction.
(1) There is no need to make an independent conception on account of
this group of income-bearing things, if an explanation can be given that
will dispose of them in a simpler way. Here are two houses lived in by the
owners in two neighboring towns. They are called consumption goods, bearing
no income. Owner A moves into another house, paying $300 rent, letting his
own for an equal sum. His house then becomes acquisitive capital. Owner B
does the same, and his house becomes capital. Chance or choice leads each
to occupy the other's house. Each, through a broker and without knowing who
his tenant is, pays the other $300 yearly, and both homes are capital. Shortly,
they move back into their own houses, which at once cease to be capital;
and the "income" of each man is reduced $300.
The puzzle is an old one, It compels us to say that a thing becomes capital
or ceases to be capital not became of any change in its physical or economic
nature, not became it is more or less serviceable to the community, not became
the use to which it is put is altered, but simply because the man who owns
it does or does not happen to be the one who enjoys that me. Now Böhm-Bawerk
himself, in his interest theory, has given us a hint of the way such an absurdity
can be avoided without the me of a separate concept,(61*) though he does
not see the application possible here. The person who rents a house buys
the "material services" of the thing during a definite period.
The whole value of the house is simply the sum of a long series of uses.
To the logical eye, though not to the technical eye of the law, the tenant
or user is the owner of the thing during the time, with only such conditions
as will insure its safe keeping and return at the close of the period. It
may be looked upon as a sale to the tenant of a use or a group of uses defined
by a period of time, and with the agreement to return the use-bearer when
a group that has not been purchased begins to mature. The value of the unpurchased
uses does not appear in the transaction, but they are bound up with the use-bearer
that is given and returned. The dancer is often compelled to deposit the
price of the masquerade suit when he takes it out. After the ball is over,
his subjective valuation having fallen, he is the gainer by returning it
at an agreed price which to the costumer represents its worth as stock to
him. The latter keeps such things in stock because there are, on an average,
enough such sales to pay his trouble, expenses, and a return on that amount
of stock. Such rented consumption goods, being owned for the time by the
user, form, then, no exception to the general class of consumption goods.
The income of the dealer or the house owner is explained as a profit gained
in exchange, like that of any other retail merchant, and includes a payment
for services, risk, and income from stock employed. To explain such transactions
as the sale of a group of uses (which is actually the temporary sale of the
use-bearer) is entirely consistent with Böhm-Bawerk's treatment of interest,
and makes needless the elaborate distinction between private and social capital.
(2) The foregoing would seem to be a valid reply, at all events as an
argumentum ad hominem, to Böhm-Bawerk; but it may appear to some to
be too elaborate and artificial. The distinction in question may then be
attacked on the still stronger round that it confuses things economic and
legal. It is based on an unclear view of the relations of economic and contract
interest. Let us look at this distinction. Contract interest is the interest
actually paid by one person to another as the result of an agreement. Economic
interest is the advantage attributable to the possession and use of a thing
during a given period. regardless of its ownership. There is economic interest
when a man uses his own plough to raise a crop or his own storeroom as a
place of business.(62*) Now, in the case of all the things included under
social (productive) capital, contract is based on and tends to conform to
economic interest. In all such cases it is economic interest that we seek
to explain logically through the economic nature of the goods. Contract interest
is a secondary problem, -- a business and legal problem, -- as to who shall
have the benefit of the income arising with the possession of the goods.
It is closely connected with the question of ownership. Only by accident,
mistaken judgment, or old agreements, can the contract interest connected
with social capital continue when economic interest does not. The two are
related as cause and effect. Yet in the case of the relatively small group
of consumption goods let for hire there is in the current view here represented
by Böhm-Bawerk only contract interest, there being supposed to be no
economic interest on which it is based. The economist's problem in distribution
is essentially an impersonal one, to determine the economic contribution
regardless of the question of legal ownership. Here, if it be held that there
is no economic interest or contribution, we have an anomalous case where
the final answer to the interest problem must contain a mixture of economic
and legal elements. No solution of this contradiction will, I believe, be
found short of the view that contract and economic interest are normally
inseparable. By "normally" I mean that no man contracts to pay
interest, or, being free to choose, actually does pay it, unless he has reason
to believe that he thereby will gain the benefit of what must be called economic
interest of a somewhat greater amount.
(3) This brings us to another objection to the distinction between social
and private capital; namely, that it involves a wrong conception of the nature
of income. I shall maintain that income must be looked upon as a series or
group of satisfactions, not as a series or group of material things. Though
scattered authority may be found for this view, it is at variance with the
views alike of Böhm-Bawerk, of Clark, and of Fisher, as well as those
of the great majority of economists, and requires explanation and defence.
The thesis is that the economic goods which are "produced" either
by human effort or by the material services of goods must, in their last
analysis, be looked upon as satisfactions. Böhm-Bawerk notices this
view as expressed by Roscher, and rejects it;(63*) yet the view is one peculiarly
in harmony with the psychological treatment of value which Böhm-Bawerk
favors. Indeed, it seems to me the view to which that value theory logically
and inevitably leads. Roscher fails to apply this thought consistently, as
Böhm-Bawerk rightly shows;(64*) and with that we will not concern ourselves.
The view suggested looks upon all material goods as means of production or
capital, their value being derived from the states of satisfaction to which
they minister or which they enhance, Böhm-Bawerk's objection to this
lacks validity. He says: "Any unbiassed person can see how unfortunate
this is. Without due cause it obliterates the very important distinction
between the production of goods which satisfy want and their consumption.
It christens, for example, the idler as a zealous producer, always thinking
how he may produce the personal goods of satiety, of ease, of contentment,
and so on." It needs only to be replied to this that the idler in such
case would be wrongly christened. The term "means of production"
must be confined to objective means of producing a subjective state, not
to subjective states, to Buddhistic dreams that unite the dreamer with Nirvana.
The pleasure of basking in the sun is a fact of which economic theorists
must take note; but that pleasure can be secured usually by the use of free
goods, and thus is not an economic satisfaction, it becomes an economic satisfaction
when it is conditioned on the control of some scarce material agent or can
be secured only by effort. The test, then, of economic personal goods or
satisfactions is dependence on either objective things or persons, or on
reaction against the outer world by the man seeing the satisfaction. If the
objection of Böhm-Bawerk is urged beyond the extreme and inapplicable
example he has given, and is applied to the personal services of one man
for another, it leads to the old and abandoned distinction between productive
and unproductive labor. We do christen many men "as jealous producers
because they are producing the personal goods of satiety," -- in other
men. Such services must be counted as ephemeral forms of wealth, enjoyed
or consumed at the moment of their production. This is no more obliterating
the distinction between production and consumption than eating a hot cake
fresh from the griddle obliterates that distinction. The two things are as
logically separable in thought when they occur simultaneously as when a second
or a decade intervenes. We have ceased to consider it essential to "productive"
labor that it should be first embodied in material form, however fleeting.
The same untenable distinction is adhered to almost universally in the case
of the services of material goods. Their productive contributions must be
put on the same basis as those of labor, to be measured by the intensity
of the wants they aid in satisfying and the psychic states they help to produce.
The house of the mill-owner is, logically considered, producing directly,
his mill is producing indirectly; for only after a devious journey will the
contribution of the mill reach its goal in the satisfaction of wants. Our
economic book-keeping can be made to balance only when real income be looked
upon as a flow of pleasure in all cases, not as a flow of goods in some and
a flow of pleasures in others, as is done generally now.
(4) This view makes possible the correction in the concepts of private
and social capital of another fault which calls for our fourth and last objection
to this part of the almost universally accepted treatment. The fault is this.
Interest is looked upon as connected with a special class of goods: it must
be recognized to be connected with everything of value.(65*) The value of
anything is built up on its uses or services to men. Wherever there is a
postponed use, that use is subject to a discount. Its present worth is less
than its worth will be at maturity. Consider the case of consumption goods.
In the orthodox view a bushel of apples, kept by the grocer from fall till
spring, is capital, and normally shows economic interest in enhanced value.
Bought in the fall and stored in the cellar by the housewife, it is a consumption
good; and economic interest is absent. But that early purchase can only be
rationally explained as we take account of the increment of value on the
apples thus stored, and this is economic interest. Larger purchases in advance
effect, of course, economy of labor, and bring an additional motive to make
them; but this is not saying that the whole saving is wages, and that no
interest is gained.
The radical consequences of this view are evident. It erases all distinction
between the essential economic character of so-called productive and consumption
goods. The term "consumption goods" may still be conveniently retained
to mean, as at present, the material good in its final form in the hands
of the one intending to use it; but it ceases to be an essential economic
category. Every material good and every human service has value only as it
is a condition to the satisfying of a present or prospective want. The abiding
value of the diamond is built on no more substantial foundation than its
flash and sparkle. Market values are the capitalized economic contribution
of objective agents to psychic states: and these states are the final, highest,
only essential economic products.
To sum up the objections to the concepts of private and social capital:
--
(1) The distinction between them rests on a supposed difference in the
interest-bearing character of different groups of consumption goods. This
difference can be explained in a simple way that makes needless an additional
concept.
(2) The distinction between them rests on legal, not on economic grounds,
and involves a confusion of economic and contract interest.
(3) The distinction rests on an incomplete and illogical view of the
nature of income and the services of goods. The income that needs to be explained
by economic theory is the flow of objectively created pleasures coming to
the individual and the community.
(4) In these concepts the interest-bearing quality is confined to the
conventional production goods and such consumption goods as yield contract
interest. Many actions connected with "consumption goods" are left
unexplained. The interest phenomenon is found wherever there is abiding value.
Our conclusion, then, is that the distinction between social (or productive)
and private (or acquisitive) capital rests on illogical grounds. Böhm-Bawerk
thinks it a great advantage that "notwithstanding the material difference
there is between capital, the factor of production, and capital, the source
of interest, it is not necessary in [his] reading to make two conceptions
of capital that are entirely foreign to one another."(66*) We must assert
on the other hand that the two conceptions he has given us are so largely
foreign to one another(67*) that, instead of an advantage, it is a source
of much confusion that they are called by the same name, as every careful
reader of Böhm-Bawerk's work must have noted. For example, he defines
capital at the beginning of his discussion(68*) as "nothing but the
complex of intermediate products which appear on the several stages of the
roundabout journey." By this he evidently means his social capital;
and he then proceeds to show that "capital in general" -- that
is, private capital -- is something more than such a complex. The reader
is frequently in doubt which one of these different concepts is designated
when the word "capital" is used. A great advantage will be gained
when, dropping unessential distinctions, we are able to save the term from
double meanings.
V. Capital as Product: The Labor-Value Fallacy.
Thus far we have considered only the question of the uses to which
goods are put as determining whether they are capital. Böhm-Bawerk's
definition, however, in common with nearly all usage, limits the conception
of capital in another way; namely, with regard to its origin. As well private
as social capital consists of a "group of products." In the foregoing,
I have widened the term productive as applied to consumption goods; but the
products there mentioned (feelings, satisfactions), being ephemeral, do not
increase the capital stock existing at a given moment. And, being final products,
these states of feeling cannot be used in further economic processes, and
do not, therefore, widen the definition Böhm-Bawerk has given us. The
test so far applied to these concepts has been alone that of economic function.
Confining capital to material "products," as does Böhm-Bawerk,
applies an additional and distinct test, -- that of economic origin, -- and
must be separately examined.
The purpose of the adjective "produced" in the phrase "produced
means of production" is to exclude land. While conceding that there
are some good reasons for including land under capital, Böhm-Bawerk
declines to do so for the reasons which we may enumerate, as follows: --
1. Land is immovable. Capital is, for the most part, movable.
2. Land is a gift of nature, Capital is a result of labor.
3. Land cannot be increased, capital can be.
4. The social and economical position of the landlord is essentially
different from that of the capitalist.
5. Property in land and property in movables are justified on essentially
different grounds, and they are commonly attacked by quite distinct people.
6. Land is the special agent in a kind of production [agriculture?] that
is economically distinguished by many important peculiarities.
7. The income from land differs in many ways from income from capital.
8. Using capital for all material means of acquisition leaves us no name
for produced acquisitive instruments.
9. Popular usage does not put land under capital, but opposes the two.
10. Usage does not apply the term "interest" to the income
from land.(69*)
He concludes that "it is most convenient to keep land quite distinct
from other kinds of Productive wealth," and that "there is a considerable
balance in favor of defining capital as the 'produced means of acquisition,'
and against the inclusion of land."(70*)
Of this formidable list it must be said that not a reason given, considered
singly, is free from flaw, some are quite mistaken, and collectively they
are not conclusive. The worth of 1 is destroyed for purposes of definition
by the limitation "for the most part." It is not that a definition
may not be based on a difference in degree, where qualities grade off from
one extreme to another; and, if something of importance depends on the degree,
it may often be expedient to draw a line of division more or less arbitrarily
somewhere. Here, however, it is not so. Things, like houses, ditches, trees,
that are as firmly fixed as the soil itself and whose value would be quite
lost if they were moved, are, without a question, included in capital. Turning
to the other part of the statement, that land is immovable, it is found quite
as untrue. Parts of land are shifting from day to day. It is usual for those
who follow this definition to consider that a thing ceases to be land and
becomes capital the instant it is moved by man's agency or effort; but to
appeal to this to prove the point is to confound "unmoved" with
"immovable." No matter is immovable. To say that "land"
means something that has not been moved by man begs the question, and this
is evidently an untenable definition of nature or material agents. Some writers
who have followed out such reasoning have been led to narrow the essential
concept of land down to mere situation,(71*) or, differently expressed, to
the "geometric relations in which any part of it stands to other parts."(72*)
This is a very different idea from the one here defended by Böhm-Bawerk,
and would not be consistent with some of the other reasons of this list.
Reason 1 in the list appears to be an illogical use of reason 2, it being
falsely assumed that results of labor are necessarily movable in the relative
sense in which we can use that term of material things, and that gifts of
nature are immovable. No such parallelism exists, and the two reasons are
often in conflict.
Passing 2 and 3 for later and fuller consideration, we take up 4 and
5, which appeal to social and personal grounds of distinction, not to economic
and impersonal ones. Here is again a confusion of the political or legal
question of ownership with the real economic question, the function performed
or contribution made by material agents. This difference, moreover, in the
social position of landlord and capitalist, so emphasized, can be shown to
rest on accidental historical grounds which we cannot now discuss. Again,
the emphasis of this difference is largely due to the misleading terminology
which is under discussion. And, finally, I would contest the statement that
property in land and "movables" is justified on essentially different
grounds. They must be, and are by most political theorists of to-day, justified
on exactly the same ground. In 6 and 7 appeal is made to differences in economic
nature.
In reason 6 there is again the fallacy of thinking of land as a field
used for agriculture. It must be said, first, that land, in the sense of
the word under discussion, -- i.e., natural agents, -- is an indispensable
agent of the milling industry, carpentry, and every other art, as well as
of agriculture. To call land the "special" agent of agriculture
because that part of land which consists of fertile soil is necessary for
plant life is to make a very crude distinction, based on no logical principle.
At most a difference of degree only is involved, in that a larger area is
usually needed to produce a given value of food than is needed to produce
that value of other things; but the reverse is frequently true. Secondly,
it may be said that "the important peculiarities" (the chief of
which no doubt is thought of as the law of diminishing returns) here attributed
to agriculture are in no way peculiar to it. The belief that they are rests
largely on the basis of a false terminology. As to 7, likewise, we have a
begging of the question; for the differences in our ways of regarding interest
and rent are primarily due to the terminology whose correctness is under
discussion. Finally, it must be noted that, when Böhm-Bawerk comes to
explain interest from durable goods,(73*) he refutes the statement that income
from land differs in many ways from income from capital, and, "obeys
many distinct laws of its own."(74*) He then finds that the two incomes
"have one common final cause."(75*) "Land rent is nothing
but a special case of interest obtained from durable goods."(76*)
In 8, 9, and 10 the appeal is to usage which is shifting, and by no means
uniform in the direction Böhm-Bawerk assumes. As to 8, the reply is
that it will be an advantage not to designate by special names the group
mentioned if it is shown, as will be done later, that such a group should
not, either for logical or practical purposes, be marked off from the other
parts of capital, indeed, it is one of the most important advantages of a
different terminology that it gets rid of the figment in question. Reasons
9 and 10 contain doubtful statements. Popular usage and economists, even
those who favor Böhm-Bawerk's terminology, in many cases class land
under capital, speaking of the investment of capital in land, and reckoning
the land with the man's capital thereafter. So, when a loan is made in money,
we are always told that the thing really borrowed is what the money buys:
if machines, then it is really these for which interest is paid; if a farm,
then it is this for which interest is paid. The moment you give the money
aspect to the loan, no attempt is made to distinguish between the income
from land and the income from other material agents.
I have left to the last reasons 2 and 3, which, stated together, read
that land is a gift of nature and cannot be increased, while capital is a
result of labor and can be increased. This thought is the central one in
the distinction: it is the parent of all the other reasons; and we here trace
to their source the errors just considered. The trail of the serpent, the
mark of the labor theory of value, is over the whole treatment of capital
as the product of former labor. Böhm-Bawerk does not escape it. He has
indeed given a most able refutation of that theory,(77*) and takes frequent
opportunities to stamp it with his disapproval. In his later volume he says
that the phrase "stock of accumulated labor" is a metaphor,(78*)
and, again, that it is employing a mere "figure of speech" to speak
of capital as "previous labor" or "stored-up labor."(79*)
In refuting socialist views, he has shown that capital "is not exclusively
'previous labor'";(80*) but he is not free from his own criticism when
he adds: "but it is partly and, indeed, as a rule, it is principally,
'previous labor'; for the rest, it is valuable natural power stored up for
human purposes."(81*) Later he again makes greater limitations on the
proposition, and says: "The asserted 'law,' that the value of goods
is regulated by the amount of the labor incorporated in them, does not hold
at all in the case of a very considerable proportion of goods; in the case
of the others, does not hold always, and never holds exactly. These are the
facts of experience with which the value theorists have to reckon."(82*)
In these statements we have the view that the value of capital is not in
proportion to previous labor, and that capital owes its value partly to scarce
and valuable natural powers. The same idea appears elsewhere. "Capital
-- to keep the same form of expression -- is 'stored-up labor,' but it is
something more: it is also stored-up valuable natural power."(83*) The
part attributed to natural powers reaches at times the vanishing-point as
Böhm-Bawerk shows;(84*) but he does not draw the obvious inference that
the part of labor reaches at times the vanishing-point, and that many products,
many things classed by him as capital, are exclusively "stored-up"
natural powers. Why continue to apply the phrase "products of labor"
more than "products of nature" to those things which owe to labor
proportions of their value varying from all to nothing? Where there is no
labor, would Böhm-Bawerk cease to call the thing capital? Certainly
not, must be the answer, if that is the only difference. To take his own
illustration, used against Rodbertus for another purpose: "If a lump
of solid gold in the shape of a meteoric stone falls on a man's field,"(85*)
will it not be capital as much as any other piece of gold? According to proposition
2, which we are criticising, it would not be capital, but land, being a "gift
of nature."
In truth, Böhm-Bawerk does not concern himself about any such difficulties,
but speaks literally of capital in the very phrase he has called a metaphor.
He says, "The next stage of the controversy brings us to the question
whether we are to give the name of capital only to the products of labor
that serve for acquisition, the 'previous stored-up labor,' or are to include
land."(86*) Again, he approves the same usage when he says, "Mill
has so far yielded to the pressure of facts as to admit that capital is itself
the product of labor, and that its instrumentality in production is, therefore,
in reality, that of labor in an indirect shape."(87*) It seems to Böhm-Bawerk
self-evident that capital is produced, "Every child knows that a piece
of capital, say a hammer, must be produced if it is to come into existence."(88*)
Now there might be some uncertainty, taking the sentence alone, as to just
what is meant here by "produced"; but the context shows that this
means just what the last-quoted sentence does, that capital is produced by
labor. In the discussion of the roundabout method of production he consciously
omits(89*) from the productive powers the uses of land "for the sake
of simplification", and assumes that the annual endowment of powers
consists only of "labor years." There is the danger in this omission
that it may accustom the author and his readers to the thought that capital
indeed consists of stored-up labor alone. In fact, most products are due
to the use of both sources of production; but supposing he had omitted "for
the sake of simplification" the labor years, and had assumed that the
productive powers of land alone produced all goods. Such cases, in fact,
occur where a fixed flow of goods from natural agents has an annual value
without the aid of man. Yet it probably never would have occurred to Böhm-Bawerk
to speak of such goods as products if, as is usually the case, they were
not fully fitted for consumption, hence were intermediate goods. I have looked
in vain not only in his writings, but through economic literature, for an
admission that capital may be a "product" of unassisted nature
as fully as it can be the product of labor. Yet there seems no valid reason
why that view should not be held, the only reason why it is not being that
the labor theory of value still influences the thoughts and utterances of
men.
Our immediate study, let us recall, is the validity of a distinction
between capital and land, on the ground that the one is and the other is
not the product of labor. We have just seen the difficulty of applying it
in the case of capital. We must now note that Böhm-Bawerk gives up the
attempt to apply it strictly to land. He says that improvements on land,
so far as they are completely incorporated with it, "are to be kept
separate from capital for the same reasons which made us keep land itself
separate from capital."(90*) Evidently, the author deceives himself.
He has forgotten one of the most important reasons for the distinction, the
one we are discussing; namely, that capital is the result of labor, and land
is not. In this case he is classing the improvements with land, not because,
but in spite of the fact that they are the results of labor. He sees the
difficulty, and in a note says: "I may be accused of want of logic here
on the ground that such improvements are always products which serve towards
further production, and therefore come under our definition of capital."(91*)
But he argues, "The criticism is correct as to the letter, but wrong
as to the spirit." What can the spirit of the distinction be that is
so opposed to the words of the definition? We get this answer: "A stay
propped up against a tree is certainly not the tree itself, but an outside
body. But who would still call it an outside body if after some years it
had grown inseparable from the tree?"(92*) So far as this has any application
at all, it disproves what the author wishes to support; for we should not
call a stick around which the tree had grown a part of the tree. The tree
has the unity of life and organization, and the stay is no part of it. The
essential thing for us, however, is that here also is a set of cases in which
Böhm-Bawerk finds it practically impossible to make the distinction
between capital and land depend on whether their source is in labor. Though
the source of their value is in labor, some things are to be classed with
natural agents because they are physically inseparable from natural agents.
May we not ask why, if the labor is incorporated in the land, does not the
land become capital? In some cases a touch of labor is all that is needed
to "produce" goods of large value from natural materials, which
are then called capital. Why call a combination of natural agents and labor
land at one time and capital at another? A satisfactory reason, if there
be one, has never yet been given.
To sum up the objections to the attempt to make the distinction between
land and capital rest on the absence or presence of labor: --
1. Some capital, things treated as such by Böhm-Bawerk and others,
is not the result of labor at all, -- for example, the meteoric lump of gold,
the annual crop of fruits on an untied field, the yield of a mineral spring.
2. It is not logical to call capital a result or product of labor, any
more than to call it a result or product of land. Nearly all capital owes
in part its economic existence to labor; but its value is not measured by
the "amount of labor," whatever that may mean, any more than it
is measured by the amount of uses of land. In fact, we have no way of expressing
the amount of labor or of uses of land, except through their value.
3. If the mere presence of labor in producing the present values is what
is meant by "production," then, practically, all land must be classed
as capital; for there is little of it that has not had its value enhanced
by labor applied to it.
4. The attempt to distinguish between the part of the value of a material
thing that is due to labor and the part that is due to nature, keeping thus
nature (or land) and capital distinct, is vain when once the labor has been
spent. This is recognized by Böhm-Bawerk in certain cases, like permanent
improvements on agricultural fields; but this case differs in no essential
from every other case where scarce natural materials are united with labor.
It is purely arbitrary to call some such combinations land, and others capital.
5. Finally, it is not true that land, as understood by the business man
or the economist when he really comes to his problem, consists only of the
gifts of nature. Large areas are made and reclaimed, and then are treated
precisely the same way as the land that exists little changed since coming
from nature's hand.
The reasons are so many and conclusive against this distinction that
only the influence of the labor theory of value over those who think themselves
emancipated from it can explain the persistence of the error. Yet this distinction
is of the essence of Böhm-Bawerk's concept of capital, A consistent
capital concept never can be based upon it.
VI. A Restatement of the Capital Concept.
We have seen(93*) that Böhm-Bawerk holds the view that capital
should be taken to consist of concrete goods, and that he opposes strongly
any attempt to make "some kind of abstraction the essence of capital."(94*)
He does not think that capital should be spoken of as a "sum of value"
or as "circulating power" or as "purchasing power."(95*)
He believes that capital consists of "the common material goods called
mills, looms, ploughs, locomotives." It is these, and not "an immaterial
sum of value," which "can grind corn, or spin yarn, or plough up
land, or carry a load."(96*) We have seen that the attack of Clark on
the work of Böhm-Bawerk assumes that the concrete conception is the
one that Böhm-Bawerk makes use of, and that it is a false one. Our criticism
of Böhm-Bawerk's treatment is on a different line; namely, that he has
not one, but two concepts of capital,(97*) and that while defining capital
as if it could be spoken of without reference to value or the use of value
expressions, he employs a value concept almost entirely in his reasoning
on the interest problem, He makes a shift without being conscious of it,
and makes use of the concept which Clark criticises him for ignoring.
In the concept of capital must be united both the thought of concrete
things and that of their value, for their quantity is only measurable in
a way that permits of comparison in terms of value. There is nothing metaphysical
or abstract about this; it is what business men are doing constantly. They
do not attempt to compare amounts of capital by physical standards of measurement.
Things which lose their value are no longer counted as capital, no matter
how large their amount. A change in the quality involving a change in value
or in value of a given quality is at once counted as a change in the quantity
of capital. And the idea of capital is carried over to all things of value,
regardless of the question of the origin of the good, Böhm-Bawerk illustrates
this usage frequently, for example, when he speaks of the "capital value
of land,"(98*) and, again, in making use of the word "capitalization"
in explaining the value of land and interest arising from it.(99*)
The business man, followed by the economist when he comes to discuss
practical problems, starts with the thought of a man with a sum of money
to spend for buying goods; and this buying is called: 'investing', his capital,
or, as the word originally meant "clothing," the money in the form
of other material things. When the money is thus "invested," it
may be in the form of machines, buildings, lands, products on which labor
has been employed. If the investment has been fortunate, we say, comparing
the values with the value of the money expended, that the capital has increased.
Now there is of course some danger of confusing capital with money, but no
more than in every case where money is used to express the value of other
goods. What is the capital? Either the money or the thing whose value is
expressed in money, Money is itself a concrete thing, one in which the value
of other things is expressed. It is this expression and measurement of market
value which is the essence of the capital concept in much business usage,
as well as in most economic discussion, no matter what may be the formal
definition. This must be recognized in our definition. Capital, in our conception,
is an aspect of material things, or, better, it consists of material things
considered in one aspect, -- their market value. -- It is under this aspect
that men have come more and more to look at wealth. The growth of a money-economy
has made it more and more convenient to compare and measure the value of
dissimilar things in terms of dollars. Things are thus capitalized. A writer,
tracing the development of the wealth concept, has well pointed out that
at one time wealth was looked upon as consisting of things of use to the
owner, lands, flocks, herds, -- use-values, to use the old phrase, -- but
that now it is looked upon as made up of things having exchange value, estimated
in terms of the general standard of value in the community.(100*) He would
confine the term "wealth" to this latter concept, leaving the former
without any special name; while the proposal here is to confine the term
"wealth" to the former concept, and apply to the latter the term
"capital." We thus adhere as closely as possible to popular usage.
We should thus speak of a man's wealth as consisting of a number of acres
of land, a herd of horses or cattle, a number of machines or ships; but we
should say that his capital consisted of so many thousand dollars' worth
of land, cattle, and the like. We say that a company has a capital of so
many thousand dollars, and it is invested in buildings and machinery. The
distinction between nominal capital and paid-up capital, and that between
the capital stock consisting of paper certificates or shares and the capital
of valuable material things, present no serious difficulties, wealth and
capital consist of precisely the same things. Wealth is the popular expression
for goods the exact valuation of which is not stated. Capital is merely the
ordinary market value expression of wealth. As we cannot give to the value
of anything an arithmetical expression except in terms of some other concrete
thing, we find it most convenient to express it in terms of money. The increase
or decrease of capital is not measured by any ultimate standard. The changes
in its money expression do not necessarily reflect changes in the welfare
of the community or of the individual. Over periods of time changes in the
quantity of capital can only be determined in a conventional way, by men's
agreeing to accept one commodity or group of commodities as a standard. But
at any moment the different portions of capital are homogeneous, and can
be compared, added, or subtracted as we see men doing every day in business.
The term "property," again, is loosely used in place of wealth
or capital, but can be clearly distinguished from them as the legal, not
the economic, aspect of valuable material things. In short, "property"
has as its essence the idea of legal right; and in connection with material
things the important right is that of control. Ownership is simply a greater
or less degree of control, The term " property," meaning legal
rights of control, is broader; that is, extends to more things than the terms
"wealth" or "capital," for it includes patent rights,
legal monopolies, valuable agreements from men to do or not to do certain
things, all having the common feature that the value is not attached to or
connected with or attributed to a material thing, but is due to the legal
right to control or limit some person's action. It seems inadvisable to try
to make the content of wealth as large as that of property by considering
that men become wealth to the degree that their rights are limited in the
interest of others.(101*) To illustrate the use of the terms "wealth,"
"capital," and "property," we would say that a stock
of goods is wealth, it is (or it represents) a capital of $10,000, and it
is the property of Jones, and the property is worth $10,000. If Brown holds
a mortgage of $5,000 on the property, however the lawyers may look at it,
we must consider that Jones's property (or right) is only of the value of
$5,000. The property of Brown and that of Jones are both found within the
capital of $10,000, and in total value cannot exceed it. The value of the
property owned never can exceed the capital that is the object of the legal
right. Many absurdities in our laws of taxation have resulted from confusing
the economic view of wealth with the legal question of ownership, and of
confusing, still less excusably the mere paper evidences of legal rights
with the wealth to which those rights apply.
To restate the definition that has here been arrived at: Capital is economic
wealth whose quantity is expressed in a general value unit. It is used as
applying to a single thing or to a group of things. There is no place in
it for the distinction, the inconsistencies of which have been discussed,
between individual and social capital. We do not call the services of thing
that minister directly to satisfaction unproductive while calling the personal
services of men productive, even where nothing material results. We do not
retain the distinction between consumption and production goods as essential
in economic discussion. All valuable thing of more than momentary duration
are "intermediate goods," are capital, in that they are valuable
became designed to satisfy future wants. While the definition thus sweeps
away any limitation on the content of capital became of a difference in future
me, it likewise sweeps away any limitation because of a difference in the
origin or source of its value. Capital is not thought of as made up only
of goods whose value is the result of labor. It has been shown that the prevailing
distinction between "natural agents" and "produced agents"
of production involves radical defects of logic and is practically not maintained.
This definition is emancipated from the false labor theory of value. In regard
to the contending views, -- first, that capital consists of concrete goods,
and, second, that it is the value of goods, -- the definition harmonizes
them by defining capital as consisting of the concrete things, but only when
considered as homogeneous and comparable units of value.
I would not exaggerate the significance of the change here proposed in
the capital concept, yet it would be folly to ignore the consequences its
acceptance would involve for economic theory. Text-books must be rewritten,
and many questions must be re-examined. This is not because the concept is
unused by the older writers, but because they have used it without recognizing
how different it was from their formal definitions and the concept employed
in other parts of their work. Many students of recent years have felt the
need of a readjustment of the leading economic concepts. This concept requires
and makes possible such a readjustment. The current theories of land value,
of rent, of interest, to a greater or less extent rest on the unsound ideas
which have been criticised throughout this paper. On another occasion the
writer will attempt to state the outlines of an economic system of thought
in harmony with the capital concept here presented.
NOTES:
1. We will note later his abandonment of this idea, calling the rent of land "interest" (Positive Theory, 355) and ascribing interest to all consumption goods, even those not included in capital. Ibid., 350.
2. Positive Theory, p. 24, ff.
3. Ibid. p. 42. ff.
4. Ibid., p. 27.
5. Ibid., p. 31, ff.
6. Positive Theory, pp. 43-50.
7. Ibid., p. 31.
8. Ibid., p. 38.
9. Positive Theory, p. 50.
10. Ibid., p. 60.
11. Ibid., Preface, p. xxiii.
12. E.g., Horace White on "Böhm-Bawerk on Capital" Political Science Quarterly, vii. 133-148; General Walker, "Böhm-Bawerk's Theory of Interest" in Quarterly Journal of Economics, vi. 309-416.
13. "The Genesis of Capital." Yale Review, ii. 302-315; "The Origin of Interest" Quarterly Journal of Economics, ix. 257.
14. Publications of the American Economic Association, iii. (1888).
15. Positive Theory, pp. 33, 34.
16. Yale Review, ix, 307.
17. Publications of American Economic Association, iii. 91.
18. Yale Review, ii. 308.
19. Quarterly Journal of Economics, ix, 257.
20. Quarterly Journal of Economics, ix, 116.
21. Ibid., 380.
22. Ibid., 263.
23. Positive Theory, pp. 17-23.
24. Quarterly Journal of Economics, ix, 258.
25. Yale Review, ii, 304.
26. A fuller discussion of this point is given later, p. 21.
27. Yale Review, ii, 307.
28. Publications of American Economic Association, iii, 96, 112.
29. Yale Review, ii, 309.
30. Ibid., 303, 304.
31. Yale Review, ii, 309. I must dissent from Clark's opinion that the term "abstinence" is, in the discussion of value theories, to be applied only to the first set of saving. See this view in Quarterly Journal, ix, 200, 261. In a more useful sense it is a power of choice that is continuously present during the foregoing of the right to consume wealth, at every moment during which a man could convert the principal of interest-bearing capital into a series of present enjoyment.
32. This point is treated more fully later.
33. Yale Review, ii, 309.
34. Ibid., 312.
35. This has already been observed by Fisher, Economic Journal, vi. 590.
36. Yale Review, ii, 309.
37. See further on this, infra, pp. 15-16.
38. Quarterly Journal of Economics, ix, 124, 125.
39. Yale Review, ii, 312.
40. This is a somewhat different presentation of Böhm-Bawerk's argument in Quarterly Journal of Economics, ix, 125-128.
41. Yale Review, ii, 310, 311.
42. Böhm-Bawerk appears to have very much the same conception of products ripening into consumption goods, in his circles of production periods. See Positive Theory, 93, 106-108.
43. Yale Review, ix, 312.
44. Yale Review, ii, 307.
45. Ibid.
46. Publications of American Economic Association, iii, 11.
47. Yale Review, ii, 308.
48. Quarterly Journal of Economics, ix, 273.
49. This article was in the editor's hands before the appearance of Professor Clark's latest work, The Distribution of Wealth. The views of the author on the capital concept there expressed show no essential change from those here examined, and the criticism stands as first written.
50. In three article, Economic Journal, vi, 509, vii, 199, 511 (18196-97).
51. Ibid., vi, 513.
52. Ibid., p. 514.
53. Economic Journal, vi, 513.
54. Ibid., p. 530.
55. E.g., at the very outset, Economic Journal, vi, 513.
56. See as to Clark, supra, p. 14.
57. Economic Journal, vi, 514, ff.
58. Economic Journal, vi, 534.
59. Surpa, p. 9.
60. Quarterly Journal of Economics, ix, 253.
61. Especially in Positive Theory, 339-349.
62. I should add, if the income is estimated as a percentage of the capital value.
63. Positive Theory, p. 44.
64. Ibid., p. 45.
65. Here we develop some of the thoughtful suggestions of Fisher, though differing with his view in ways already suggested. See Economic Journal, vii, 525.
66. Positive Theory, p. 40.
67. Ibid., p. 61. He says here, flatly contradicting his own words just quoted: "Substantially, (the conception of social capital) is a quite independent conception. In every essential respect (in definition, in scientific employment, and in scope) it stands on entirely independent principles."
68. Ibid., p. 23.
69. Positive Theory, pp. 55, 56.
70. Ibid., p. 56.
71. Commons, Distribution of Wealth, p. 29.
72. Marshall, 2d ed., p. 198.
73. Positive Theory, pp. 339-357.
74. Ibid., p. 55.
75. Ibid., p. 337.
76. Ibid., p. 355. The explanation given by Böhm-Bawerk is open to serious criticism.
77. Capital and Interest, passim, but particularly pp. 237-387.
78. Positive Theory, p. 33.
79. Positive Theory, p. 53.
80. Capital and Interest, p. 341.
81. Ibid., p. 341.
82. Ibid., p. 387.
83. Positive Theory, p. 90.
84. Capital and Interest, p. 341.
85. Capital and Interest, p. 338.
86. Positive Theory, p. 55.
87. Ibid., p. 96.
88. Ibid., p. 117.
89. E.g., Ibid., pp. 89 and 106.
90. Positive Theory, p. 65.
91. Ibid., p. 65.
92. Positive Theory, p. 65.
93. See supra, p. 6.
94. Positive Theory, pp, 33, 34.
95. Ibid., pp. 58, 59.
96. See other definitions of capital as concrete in Positive Theory, pp. 22, 65.
97. One of which differs both from the social and the private capital; three, therefore, including both of them.
98. Positive Theory, p. 344.
99. Ibid., p. 348.
100. Charles A. Tuttle, in Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, i, 615, ff.
101. Such a view is taken by Irving Fisher, Economic Journal, vii, 206.